Reflections on the Revolution in France

by

Edmund Burke

Reflections on the Revolution in France: Section 7 Summary & Analysis

Summary
Analysis
Burke turns to Price’s comments regarding “the favorableness of the present times to […] exertions in the cause of liberty.” Burke argues that liberty is rather “a possession to be secured than […] a prize to be contended for.” He wonders, “What is that cause of liberty, and what are those exertions in its favor, to which the example of France is so singularly auspicious?” The members of the Revolution Society seem to look with contempt on those aspects of English governance which Burke has supposed to be England’s “glory.” They disdain the supposed “inequality in our representation,” hoping for the provocation of “some great calamity” which will encourage England to throw off this yoke.
Here, Burke questions Price’s claim that “exertions” on behalf of liberty are appropriate, because such implies that liberty must be fought for. He rather holds that England is a better repository of liberty than France is, because it has carefully guarded liberty for generations, and no exertions are necessary. But Price and other radical Englishmen overlook this, favoring the model of France.
Themes
Nature, Tradition, and Wisdom Theme Icon
Revolution and Reform Theme Icon
Given the Revolution Society’s contempt for Britain’s own constitution and government, it’s not surprising that they now look to France for another model. They are so obsessed that it’s fruitless to talk to them about their ancestors’ practices or their country’s long-tested constitution: “They despise experience as the wisdom of unlettered men […] they have ‘the rights of men.’”
The “rights of men” refers to the 1789 revolutionary Declaration of the Rights of Man, which Burke disdains as disconnected from history and concrete reality. Those who favor these abstract “rights” overlook the wisdom embedded in lived experience.
Themes
Nature, Tradition, and Wisdom Theme Icon
Revolution and Reform Theme Icon
Theory vs. Practicality Theme Icon
Quotes
Burke explains that he does not deny “the real rights of men.” People have a right to justice, to the fruits of their labor, and whatever they desire to do without trespassing on the rights of others. Burke denies, however, that each has a right to “the share of power, authority, and direction” in the management of the state. He argues that one of the conventions of civil society is that “no man should be judge in his own cause.” That is, he gives up some of his liberty in order to secure some of it.
Burke affirms that basic human rights do exist. However, the possession of such rights does not grant someone a place in the government of society. He refers to the traditional view that people should not determine the outcome of their own case—writ large, this suggests that people in general should not be involved in their own government.
Themes
Nature, Tradition, and Wisdom Theme Icon
Revolution and Reform Theme Icon
Burke uses the above as an example of the point that government doesn’t rest on clear, abstract “natural rights,” because the “perfection” of such rights “is their practical defect.” Government is, rather, “a contrivance of human wisdom to provide for human wants.”
Burke argues that government is inherently practical. It’s a means of ensuring that people get what they lack. It cannot rest on abstractions, contrary to the revolutionary view.
Themes
Revolution and Reform Theme Icon
Theory vs. Practicality Theme Icon
Get the entire Reflections on the Revolution in France LitChart as a printable PDF.
Reflections on the Revolution in France PDF
For example, one such “want” is “a sufficient restraint upon […] passions.” Both individual and collective passions must necessarily be thwarted sometimes, for the good of both individuals and the whole; only someone besides themselves has the power to do this. But the circumstances of this vary greatly, so it doesn’t make sense to create an “abstract rule” about them. This is part of why governance is so difficult—it “requires a deep knowledge of human nature.”
Burke argues that government requires a knowledge of particular circumstances, as well as the recurrent truths about human behavior; these are not things to which an abstract rule can be applied without allowance for interpretation.
Themes
Nature, Tradition, and Wisdom Theme Icon
Theory vs. Practicality Theme Icon
Quotes
Burke goes on, asking, “What is the use of discussing a man’s abstract right to food or to medicine? The question is upon the method of procuring and administering them,” which is better answered by a farmer or physician, “rather than the professor of metaphysics.” A “plausible scheme” may turn out to have “lamentable conclusions”; likewise, “obscure” causes might end up being critical to a nation’s prosperity.
Burke famously makes the point that there is no use talking about abstract rights to concrete things; government should be in the business of providing such things, not theorizing about them. And an airtight academic scheme might not be the best means of provision.
Themes
Theory vs. Practicality Theme Icon
Because, then, “the science of government” is so inherently practical, it requires experience—far more than the experience of even a single wise person. Even such a wise person ought to show “infinite caution” in “pulling down an edifice which  has answered in any tolerable degree for ages the common purposes of society,” or trying to rebuild without the aid of time-tested models.
Government, then, is not a matter of simply placing the smartest people into the right positions. Rather, it balances on collective wisdom, and adapting that long-tested wisdom to present situations. It requires careful deliberation, not hasty changes.
Themes
Nature, Tradition, and Wisdom Theme Icon
Revolution and Reform Theme Icon
Theory vs. Practicality Theme Icon
Quotes
Burke goes on to suggest that “the pretended rights of these theorists are all extremes”; even when theoretically correct, they often prove “morally and politically false. “The rights of men defy precise definitions, and government can only put them into practice through compromise, never with exactness.
Burke further explains that a theory can be true, but difficult or impossible to put into practice, and thus not serviceable for society. Broad definitions often fail to account for the needs of particular people.
Themes
Nature, Tradition, and Wisdom Theme Icon
Theory vs. Practicality Theme Icon
Burke wonders if people, in their revolutionary fervor, have become so taken up with the “rights of man” that they’ve forgotten human nature. Such an obsession, cautions Burke, is dangerous. To such people, “plots, massacres, assassinations, seem […] a trivial price for obtaining a revolution.” They seem to be satisfied with nothing less than a “grand spectacle,” lulled by the privileges of security and prosperity. Burke argues that the present condition of France’s government is a “burlesque” and “perversion,” of which its own participants must have felt ashamed.
Burke portrays the French Revolution as a spectacle in which people have been thoughtlessly swept away. It’s disconnected from the real needs and nature of people and therefore more likely to satisfy their appetites in the short run while harming their long-term security.
Themes
Nature, Tradition, and Wisdom Theme Icon
Revolution and Reform Theme Icon