Leviathan

by

Thomas Hobbes

Leviathan: Chapter 42 Summary & Analysis

Summary
Analysis
To understand what “POWER ECCLESIASTICALL” is and who has it, Hobbes says one must understand the time both before and after the “Conversion of Kings,” before which Christianity was not allowed. Before Christ’s Ascension and the later Conversion of Kings, the Apostles had ecclesiastical power, which means they were ordained to preach Christianity and convert others. After the Apostles, ecclesiastical power was again given to “Ministers of God,” or those ordained with the Holy Spirit and authorized to teach and preach God’s Word.  
Christianity was not allowed in Rome prior to 313 CE. Constantine, who ruled Rome from 306 to 337 CE, was the first Roman Emperor to adhere to Christian teachings, and he converted to Christianity in 337, the same year he died. By beginning with the “Conversion of Kings” and Christ’s Ascension to Heaven, Hobbes is able to trace the line of succession of God’s ministers through time to establish authority. 
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
According to popular Christian belief, the “Person of God” is born three times. St. John says: “There be three that bear witness in heaven, the Father, the Word, and the Holy Spirit; and these Three are One.” These three are known in Holy Scripture as the “Trinity.” Hobbes, however, argues three can never be one, and in this case, the Trinity more rightly signifies “three Persons.” God represented by Moses is one person, and God represented by Christ is another. God represented by the Apostles is collectively a third, and in no way are any of these individual men one, other than their shared love for God, which can be said for many.    
The Holy Trinity is another sacred belief in Christianity that Hobbes argues has been largely misinterpreted. Popular Christian belief holds that God is three beings—the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit—but Hobbes maintains it is impossible for one to be three. Instead, Hobbes contends that the Holy Trinity is really three separate people (or groups of people, as is the case with the Apostles), who are authorized by God and have “Ecclesiastical,” or spiritual, power.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
In short, ecclesiastical power is the power to teach God’s Word, and Hobbes uses Christ’s power as proof of his argument. As Christ’s Kingdome is not of this world, his ministers can’t command obedience in Christ’s name, unless that minister is also a sovereign king. Christ was sent to the Jews to convince them to return to God and accept Christ as King but not until Judgement day. The time between Christ’s Ascension and the Resurrection is called a “Regeneration,” not a reign. In Matthew 19:28, Christ says: “You that have followed me in the Regeneration, when the Son of man shall sit in the throne of his glory, you shall also sit upon twelve Thrones.” Clearly, Hobbes explains, Christ was not King during this time.
Hobbes contends that only certain people have ecclesiastical power and are authorized to preach God’s Word, but even this power is limited, and, like all other forms of power, it exists only as allowed by the civil sovereign of a common-wealth. Moses was the civil sovereign of the Israelites, and Christ will be the civil sovereign of his Kindgome after the second coming. Until then, however, Hobbes argues that supreme power is one’s earthly sovereign, not God or one of his Lieutenants.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
The purpose of Christ’s ministers on this Earth is to convert others to Christianity, but this conversion is not a command, and it is not compulsory. In 2 Corinthians 1:24, St. Paul says: “Wee have no Dominion over your Faith, but are Helpers of your Joy.” Hobbes questions what one is to do if their sovereign power, such as a king or a senate, forbids their subjects to believe in Christ. To forbid one to believe or not believe in any one thing is ineffective, Hobbes says, because one’s faith is a gift from God, and it cannot be taken by any one person or persons.
Again, Hobbes draws a clear distinction between ecclesiastical power and sovereign power. Ecclesiastical power is not obligatory, whereas sovereign power is. As such, no one person can command anyone to believe or not believe in any god, even if that command is given by one’s sovereign power.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
Get the entire Leviathan LitChart as a printable PDF.
Leviathan PDF
A sovereign king can tell his subjects what to do and forbid public gatherings and practices associated with Christianity, but a king cannot change what is in his subjects’ hearts. If one is made to renounce Christ “on pain of death,” but Christ really does live in their heart, one can lie without any affront to Christ or the sovereign power, since the Law of Nature says a person cannot be forced to confess something that endangers their life. Plainly put, those who die as martyrs die needlessly. 
A sovereign power cannot order subjects to believe or disbelieve in God, just as God himself could not order the Israelites to believe in him. The Israelites had to come to God via a covenant, and it is the same for any other Christian.
Themes
Nature, War, and Civil Society   Theme Icon
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
The true definition of a martyr, Hobbes says, is one who witnessed Christ’s Resurrection, not someone who dies rather than cast away their love for Christ. In Acts 1:22, St. Peter asks: “must one be ordained to be a Martyr (that is a Witnesse) with us of his Resurrection.” In this definition of the word martyr, even if one did witness Christ’s Resurrection, this does not obligate them to die for the same cause.
Hobbes’s definition of the word martyr again suggests that scripture has been largely misinterpreted, as a martyr is usually defined as someone who is killed for their religious beliefs. In this way, Hobbes implies that most Holy Scripture, and the terms and definitions involved in it, have been misinterpreted.  
Themes
Religion Theme Icon
Literary Devices
The Apostles, like Christ, were sent to preach God’s Word, which makes them similar to a herald, or a crier, or another such person who delivers messages for a king. In such situations, a herald cannot command anyone to do anything and neither could the Apostles. The Apostles were also sent to teach. In the Book of Mark 16:15 it reads: “Goe into all the world, and Preach the Gospel to every creature.” 
This passage again underscores the limitations of ecclesiastical power. As messengers of God, Christ and the Apostles did not wield the same power as God. In this vein, if God does have a Lieutenant on Earth now—the Catholic Pope, for instance—the power of that messenger is also limited and cannot be compulsory.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
Those accepting of God’s Word can be baptized “in the name of the Father, and of the Son, and of the Holy Ghost,” which is a sign that a subject will be loyal to God and those appointed by him. Baptism is a type of covenant, but true authority is with an “Earthly Soveraign [sovereign]” until Judgement Day.
Again, Hobbes discounts the idea that God is three people (the Father, Son, and Holy Ghost) as is assumed with the Holy Trinity. For Hobbes, one body can never be divided into three; however, the power of one body can be given to three different people.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
Within ecclesiastical power is the power to give the “Keyes of the Kingdome of Heaven” to another and allow entrance into God’s Kingdome. On the flipside, one with ecclesiastical power can deny the keys to one and excommunicate another. To excommunicate is to ban someone from their church, after which other Christians are instructed to avoid them. However, a church has no power to keep anyone out of an assembly, since all places are under dominion of the common-wealth and sovereign power.
Hobbes again underscores the limitations of ecclesiastical power. While one with ecclesiastical power can technically excommunicate a member of a church and deny their entrance into God’s Kingdome, that banishment is not really enforceable until God’s second coming. In an earthly common-wealth, only the sovereign power has the authority to ban someone from an assembly. 
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
If an Apostate is excommunicated, it means nothing and has no effect. Excommunication only matters to those who believe in Christ, and it is practiced as punishment for some transgression. According to I Corinthians 5:11, “if any man that is called a Brother, be a Fornicator, or Covetous, or an Idolater, or a Drunkard, or an Extortioner, with such a one yee are not to eat.” In short, those who are found guilty of such sins are excommunicated.
In order to be excommunicated, one must first believe in God. An Apostate is someone who does not believe in religious doctrine. If one does not believe that God’s Kingdome exists and does not wish to enter into a covenant to become part of it, it is no punishment to ban them from it.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
For one to be excommunicated, they must first be a member of a Christian church. As all churches are equal in power, no one church has authority to excommunicate the members of another. Furthermore, Hobbes argues, if a sovereign power—for instance, a Prince—is a member of a Christian church, that Prince cannot be excommunicated. According to the Law of Nature, a Prince’s subjects are obligated to be in his presence when he commands it, and they can never refuse to sit and eat with him. 
Hobbes implicitly argues here that the Pope does not have the authority to excommunicate the sovereign power of another country. Henry VIII and Elizabeth I of England were both excommunicated by the Pope, but Hobbes argues the Pope never had the ecclesiastical power to do such a thing in the first place. An excommunicated Christian must be shunned by other Christians; however, it is not possible for subjects to shun their sovereign power. 
Themes
Nature, War, and Civil Society   Theme Icon
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
To recap, the power of excommunication can only go as far as the power of Apostles, which is to teach God’s Word and to covert others to his way to ensure “Salvation in the world to come.” Before civil sovereigns became Christians, St Paul visited Jews at their synagogue. In Acts 17:2-3, St. Paul “reasoned with them out of the Scriptures, […] and that this Jesus whom he preached was the Christ.” St. Paul had no authority over the Jews other than to interpret Holy Scripture as he was ordered to do by Christ.
St. Paul’s ecclesiastical power over the Jews was limited, and Hobbes argues that the ecclesiastical power of any religious entity or body is also limited. Christ ordered the Apostles to preach obedience to earthly, civil sovereigns, not to obey God above all others. Thus, a Christian in England cannot possibly be expected to obey the ecclesiastical power of the Pope over their sovereign king or queen.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
When attempting to convert Gentiles, quoting Holy Scripture was no use, as they did not believe in Christ. Thus, the Apostles used “Reason to confute [the Gentiles’] Idolatry.” In short, the Apostles persuaded the nonbelievers, and when they did, the Gentiles were converted to nothing but a belief in what the Apostles taught. This belief is reflected in the Old Testament when Christ says to the Jews: “Search the Scriptures; for in them yee thinke to have eternall life, and they are they that testifie of me.”
The reason the Apostles used and the Gentiles accepted is the very same reason God has given to all of humankind. Through this reason, the Gentiles abandoned their “Idolatry,” or false gods, and accepted the true God. This belief, however, is more applicable to one’s “eternall life,” not their present earthly life. Thus, to accept God is not to reject one’s earthly, civil sovereign.
Themes
Nature, War, and Civil Society   Theme Icon
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
Reason, Fact, and Philosophy  Theme Icon
A piece of writing can be said to be “Canonicall” in two ways. The word “Canon” signifies a “Rule” by which one guides their actions. When these “Rules” are given by a teacher or counselor to a student or friend, such words do not have the power to compel one to any given action or behavior. However, when such “Rules” are given to someone who is compelled by another to obey them, they become “Laws.” 
“Canonicall” writings, or writings that are accepted into the canon of Holy Scripture, are viewed as either “rules” or “laws.” A “rule” is a recommendation made by a teacher to a student, like honoring one’s mother and father. However, a “law” is Holy Scripture made decree by a civil sovereign, like civil laws against murder.  
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
The first piece of Holy Scripture to become law was the Ten Commandments, which God gave to Moses on tablets of stone. God delivered the Commandments to Moses, and Moses delivered them to the people. The laws that God dictated to Israel’s magistrates are known as “Judicall Law,” and Moses also delivered these laws. When Moses delivered God’s Word, these words became laws by way of Moses’s covenant with the people. 
As God’s Lieutenant on Earth, Moses was the sovereign power of the Israelites and therefore had the power to make the Ten Commandments into law. However, this power only extended over the Israelites because they agreed to the covenant.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
Moses added different laws as the Israelites readied themselves for the land of Promise, and these are known as “Second Laws.” In Deuteronomy 29:1, it is written: “The words of a Covenant which the Lord commanded Moses to make with the Children of Israel, besides the Covenant which he made with them in Horeb.” Moses made each King of Israel keep a copy of the laws, but, Hobbes says, Moses was also the “Civill Soveraign [sovereign].”
Again, Moses had the power to make God’s laws into civil laws because he was the sovereign power of the Israelites. This distinction is important to Hobbes’s argument because it supports his contention that God’s law is only civil law when it is decreed by an earthly, civil sovereign.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
There were no other laws instituted until after the captivity of the Jews, after which they entered into a covenant with Moses to accept the “Law of God.” The Old Testament was not law until this covenant, which in effect formed the common-wealth of the Jews. The New Testament, on the other hand, was not considered law until sovereign Christians deemed it so, beginning with Constantine.
Constantine was the first civil sovereign (other than Moses) to accept and follow Christianity. Constantine ruled the Roman Empire from 306 to 337 and marks the “Conversion of Kings” Hobbes refers to earlier in the chapter. As a Christian, Constantine was the first to make Holy Scripture into law, in all other instances, scripture is merely “rule.”
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
But, for the New Testament to be law wherever a common-wealth forbids it contradicts the very nature of a law. Thus, whenever any “Rule” is offered that the sovereign has not endorsed, such “Rule” can only be counsel, not compulsion. In common-wealths where God’s Word goes against the established laws, God’s Word cannot be followed. Of course, Hobbes says, while God’s Word cannot be put into practice or discussed with others in such instances, it may be secretly honored.
Again, Hobbes implies that a sovereign power can never compel a subject to disbelieve in God, even if a sovereign can make the public worship or following of God’s laws illegal. God’s law states that everyone must obey their earthly sovereign in all ways, but a sovereign can never take away the gift of faith.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
Again, the purpose of Christ’s command to the Apostles was to spread word of his Kingdome, not in this world but the next. The Apostles were to teach the people and baptize them as believers, but they did not have power to make Christ’s command into law. Instead, they taught obedience to established laws. As only a sovereign power in the civil sense can make any “Rule” into law, the Holy Scripture within the New Testament can only be considered “Law” in those common-wealths where a sovereign power has willed it so. 
This again illustrates the limitations of ecclesiastical power. Holy scripture can only be elevated from “Rule” to “Law” in those common-wealths where the civil sovereign has deemed it so, and this power is limited to that specific common-wealth. For example, while the Pope is the civil sovereign of Vatican City, the Pope is not the civil sovereign of England and cannot impose laws on Christians there.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
Therefore, ecclesiastical power is limited in many ways. In Acts 15:28, the Apostles say to the Elders: “It seemed good to the Holy Ghost, and to us, to lay upon you no greater burthen then these necessary things.” Those necessary things, according to Hobbes, are to repent, be baptized, follow the Commandments, and believe in God’s Word. 
The “necessary things” Hobbes lists here are the only things a Christian must observe to gain entrance into God’s Kingdome, and each of these things can be done while also obeying one’s civil, earthly sovereign.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
Ecclesiastical officers during the time of the Apostles were either “Magisteriall” or “Ministeriall.” “Magisteriall” officers preached to nonbelievers and administered sacraments to those they already converted. “Ministeriall” officers included the deacons who saw to the operational needs of the church. The first Magisterial officers were the Apostles, who were chosen by Christ to be martyrs—that is, to witness his Resurrection. The first non-martyr Apostle was Matthias, who was chosen by an assembly of 120 Christians, and then there was Paul and Barnabas, who, by the Church of Antioch, were made Apostles.
Hobbes makes a distinction between two types of ecclesiastical officers—those who have the power to teach and those who don’t. The first ecclesiastical officers with the power to teach were given this power by a covenant with Christ, and afterward, they were selected by an assembly of people. The Church of Antioch was one of the earliest Christian churches (located near present-day Turkey), and the assembly imbued Paul and Barnabas with the same power through their own covenant. 
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
A bishop is an “overseer” of the church, and the first Christian bishops were the Apostles. After the Apostles instituted the Elders, they, too, were known as bishops, as was any pastor, teacher, or doctor whose calling was Christ. As Apostles, Matthias, Paul, and Barnabas were authorized by the people, not Christ. Countless bishops were authorized in much the same way, as is reflected in Acts 14:23, which says “they ordained Elders in every Church.” This remains common practice even today, as new bishops are elected in Rome. 
In Hobbes’s view, bishops who were authorized directly by Christ or God had more authority than those who were authorized after Christ’s Resurrection by countless church assemblies. Thus, the Pope, having been authorized by the people, not God or Christ directly, does not have the same authority claimed by early Apostles.  
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
A minister is someone who voluntarily does business for another. Pastors within a church are known as “The Ministers of the Word,” and deacons are responsible for “Serving of Tables,” which means they serve the congregation. The very first deacons were selected by the Disciples, not the Apostles, which can be seen in Acts 6:3. “Brethren looke you out among you seven men of honest report, full of the Holy Ghost, and of Wisdome, whom we may appoint over this business.”
Hobbes again makes a distinction between ministers and deacons. Ministers have the ecclesiastical power to teach and preach, but a deacon does not. This distinction becomes increasingly important in Hobbes’s explanation of the public’s duty to finically support their ministers. Hobbes implies it is not the public’s duty to support deacons in the same way.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
According to Numbers 18:20, God said to Aaron: “Thou shalt have no inheritance in their land, neither shalt thou have any part amongst them.” Thus, the maintenance and support of ministers must come from public revenue in the form of tithes and offerings. Judas Iscariot had a purse to maintain Christ, and many of the Apostles, who were also fishermen, worked in their trade to earn money to keep them. Whenever the Apostles went out to preach, Christ did not allow them to carry any money. 
Again, Hobbes is using scripture to illustrate his point that ministers are supposed to be kept financially by the communities they serve. This point seems somewhat unimportant here, but Hobbes comes back to it at the end of Leviathan. Hobbes argues that this public support is motive for some clergy to exploit the people and the church.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
After the Ascension of Christ, Christians everywhere “lived in Common” with the money earned from their land and possessions, and they supported the Apostles with their offerings. 1 Corinthians 9:14 reads: “Even so hath the Lord appointed, that they which preach the Gospel should live of the Gospel.” Thus, Hobbes argues, it can be concluded that a church’s ministers should be maintained by the people of that church. This maintenance can be determined by each church member individually or by the entire assembly; however, to determine by entire assembly is impossible, as the assembly lacks the power to make a law. So, in common-wealths where the sovereign power does not make laws to determine a minister’s maintenance, or salary, it relies on charity.  
As no church assembly can ever have the power to make scripture law, a church assembly cannot determine a minister’s salary, and the minister must rely on charity. If the sovereign power of a common-wealth is also a Christian, that sovereign can deem any given minister’s salary as a law. Again, Hobbes later comes back to this fact and argues that Christian sovereigns can abuse this power and command higher salaries for certain ministers, like the bishops of Rome. 
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
A sovereign power of a common-wealth who is also a Christian has the right to appoint ministers. The sovereign power is the “Supreme Pastor” of their subjects, and they have the power to teach and ordain as they please. Before the Conversion of Kings, ministers and other pastors were selected and appointed by an assembly. Suppose a Christian sovereign, such as a king, passes his authority to ordain ministers within his common-wealth to another sovereign power, like the Pope in Rome. In doing so, the Christian sovereign robs himself of power.
Hobbes implies that it makes very little sense for a sovereign power to allocate any part of its power to another power, like to the Pope in Rome. In giving the Pope some of its power, a sovereign diminishes its own power, which is counterproductive to the covenant that creates it. The purpose of a common-wealth is to create a sovereign with as much power as possible. If the sovereign gives some of that power away, it isn’t as powerful as it could be. 
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
In a common-wealth, all ministers and pastors preach and teach under the authority given to them by the sovereign power, meaning a minister’s authority is “Jure Civili.” The sovereign power, however, derives their own authority to teach and preach Christianity from God, which means a sovereign’s authority is “Jure Divino.” As every sovereign power is also the “Supreme Pastor,” they can preach, teach, baptize, and administer the sacraments. Just because a sovereign power has the ability to do such things does mean they actually do them, Hobbes says. A sovereign is much too busy with the common-wealth; thus, they appoint others below them as ministers. Christ never baptized anyone, Hobbes says, but sent his Apostles and Disciples instead.
A sovereign’s power to preach is “Jure Divino,” meaning it is divine and comes directly from God. A minister’s ecclesiastical power, on the other hand, comes from the sovereign power and is “Jure Civili,” meaning their power is civil, not divine. This is an important distinction because it again illustrates that a minister can never have the ecclesiastical power to excommunicate a sovereign from the Christian Church.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
The “Imposition of Hands” is an ancient ceremony performed publicly by the Jews, in which it is made clear who, or what, is being blessed or condemned, as Jacob does when he blesses Joseph’s children. Jacob “laid his right Hand on Ephraim the younger, and his left Hand on Manasseh the first born.” In Leviticus 24:14, God orders all the blasphemers to “Lay their Hands on his head, and that all the congregation should stone him.” Christ, too, performs this ceremony in Matthew 19:13: “They brought unto him little children, that hee should Put his Hands on them, and Pray.”  
With Hobbes’s explanation of the “Imposition of Hands,” he implies that to lay hands on another in a spiritual sense does not always imply a miracle or the transfer of power, as is often assumed in popular Christian doctrine. Jacob lays his hands on the children to bless them, and God orders nonbelievers to lay their own hands on their heads to identify themselves. Christ, too, lays his hands on others to pray, not necessarily to heal or ordain. 
Themes
Religion Theme Icon
The Apostles, too, “Laid Hands” on those they ordained or prayed with. In Acts 8:17, Peter and John go to the people of Samaria and “Laid their Hands on them, and they received the Holy Ghost.” The purpose of such a ceremony, especially when ordaining a minister, is to designate the one who is receiving the power. In the case of a sovereign power, they have always had the power to teach and ordain others; thus, there is no need for the “Imposition of Hands.” 
According to Hobbes, a sovereign power does not require another power—like the Pope, for instance—to lay hands on them and imbue them with the ecclesiastical power of a minister. A sovereign has already been given this power by God, so only God can take this power away.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
A sovereign power may transfer the management of religious matters to the Pope, or they can transfers the management of religious matters to one minister or assembly within their own dominion. As the power of the Pope in Rome is universally accepted, Hobbes thinks it proper to discuss Cardinal Bellarmine and his books, De Summo Pontifice. The first of Cardinal Bellarmine’s books discusses the best form of government, which Bellarmine claims is a mix of monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy. Bellarmine claims that the best government for a church is also a mix of the three; however, he says that mix should be mostly monarchical.  
A cardinal is a high-ranking bishop of the Catholic Church (the Pope is selected from a conclave of cardinals), and Cardinal Bellarmine was a particularly important cardinal who served the Pope until Bellarmine’s death in 1621. Bellarmine wrote a treatise entitled De Summo Pontifice, in which he argued that all sovereigns of the world should be held under the ecclesiastical power of the Catholic Pope.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
Hobbes says he has already discussed that a monarchy is the best form of government, but he argues that a church’s form of government makes very little difference. It is not the purpose of a church to govern by order and command. On the contrary, the purpose of a church is to guide others and persuade through Holy Scripture. Furthermore, the Pope’s power in common-wealths that are not his own is that of a “Schoolmaster only,” not a “Master of Family.” 
According to Hobbes, the Pope only has power over his own common-wealth (Vatican City in Rome) and cannot claim power over any other sovereign or common-wealth. For instance, the Pope has no authority over the sovereign power of England or its subjects. Thus, the Pope can only guide such subjects like a “Schoolmaster” or teacher and cannot command them like a “Master” to his servants. 
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
Literary Devices
In his second book, Cardinal Bellarmine argues that St. Peter was the first bishop in Rome and that all other Popes are his successors. Many people, Hobbes says, dispute this claim. If the first bishop in Rome was the “Supreme Pastor,” that first Roman bishop was Constantine, Rome’s first Emperor, not St. Peter. Bellarmine’s third book argues whether the Pope is the Antichrist. Hobbes, however, can find no evidence to support this argument. The Jews expected a Messiah in the Old Testament, which opened them up to imposters and false prophets. The word Antichrist is properly defined as someone who claims to be Christ but isn’t; or, as someone who denies Jesus is himself the Christ. As the Pope in Rome has done neither of these two things, he cannot be rightly called the Antichrist.
Other than Moses, Constantine was the first Christian sovereign in Rome; thus, Hobbes implies that the Pope comes from a succession that begins with Constantine, not St. Peter as Cardinal Bellarmine and the Catholic Church maintain. In this light, Hobbes throws the entire succession and appointment of Popes and their authority into question. During the 16th century, many Protestants claimed the Pope was the Antichrist. Bellarmine’s third book, Antichrist, argues that the Pope is definitively not the Antichrist. In this case, Hobbes agrees with Bellarmine and finds no evidence to support such a claim.  
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
In Cardinal Bellarmine’s forth book, he argues that the Pope’s “Judgements are Infallible” and that Christ gave ecclesiastical power to the Pope in Rome. Bellarmine turns to Holy Scripture to prove his point. In Luke 22:31, Christ says to Simon: “Simon, Simon, Satan hath desired you that hee may sift you as wheat; but I have prayed for thee, that thy faith faile not, and when thou art converted, strengthen thy Brethren.” In Bellarmine’s interpretation, Christ promises that Simon’s faith will not fail as long as that faith follows that as defined by the Pope. Hobbes argues Bellarmine’s interpretation is wrong.
In Hobbes’s own interpretation of Holy Scripture, Christ only gives ecclesiastical power to his Apostles, anyone else—including the Pope in Rome—is given their ecclesiastical power by the assembly of people in which they serve. Hobbes does argue that the Pope’s power to act as minister onto his own subjects is given to him by the divine power of God; however, that power does not extend beyond the subjects of the Pope’s own common-wealth. 
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
The sovereign power alone has complete authority to define how Holy Scripture is interpreted, not the Pope. As for the Pope’s infallibility of judgement, Cardinal Bellarmine again cites Holy Scripture and John 16:13. “When the Spirit of truth is come, hee will lead you into all truth.” The implied “truth” here, Hobbes argues, is truth as it relates to salvation, not all truth in general. Thus, the Pope’s judgement concerning salvation is likely sound, but his judgement can never be completely foolproof. Even with this distinction, the Pope’s judgement concerning salvation is no more infallible than the judgement of any other devout Christian.   
As the Pope is only the sovereign power of his own common-wealth, he has no say in how Holy Scripture is interpreted in other common-wealths. Hobbes does not mean to say that there is no truth in the Pope’s words and judgement. Hobbes simply argues that it’s impossible for a person’s judgment to be “infallible.” Judgement and reason can be certain in very few circumstances (geometry for one), and no one person can claim to be right all the time.  
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
Reason, Fact, and Philosophy  Theme Icon
It has never been claimed by the church or the Pope that the Pope is the sovereign power over all the world’s Christians. Thus, all Christians are not obligated to obey the Pope. The sovereign power of a common-wealth has dominion over everyone in their common-wealth, including the Christians. Therefore, if the Pope claims to have jurisdiction over all the Christians in the world, he teaches those Christians to disobey their sovereign power, which directly contradicts the lessons taught by the Apostles in Holy Scripture. 
In Hobbes’s view, no Christian living outside the common-wealth of the Pope can be beholden to the Pope’s power. Thus, a Christian living in England is beholden to England’s sovereign power, even if that Christian is a Catholic. Hobbes argues there is no covenant that obligates all Christians to a single power; thus, all Christians are obligated to follow their individual civil sovereigns. 
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
To prove the Pope has power to institute laws, Cardinal Bellarmine cites Deuteronomy 7:12: “The man that will doe presumptuously, and will not hearken unto the Priest, (that standeth to Minister there before the Lord thy God, or unto the Judge,) even that man shall die, and thou shalt put away the evill from Israel.” Through numerous biblical passages, Bellarmine maintains that Christ gave ecclesiastical power to the Pope and no one else, but Hobbes disagrees. It is only Christian sovereigns who can claim power to govern from God or Christ. Any minister who has ecclesiastical power derives that power from the sovereign. “All lawful Power is of God,” Hobbes contends, but the absolute power of a Pope is not lawful.   
Hobbes does not dispute that the Pope has the power to institute laws; however, the Pope only has the power to institute laws within his own common-wealth. Hobbes argues that ecclesiastical power is given to every Christian sovereign, not just the Pope, by the divine power of God. As Hobbes points out earlier, a sovereign’s ecclesiastical power is “Jure Divino,” whereas as a minister’s ecclesiastical power is “Jure Civili” and comes from the sovereign power. In this way, all “lawful Power is of God,” but the total power of Pope proposed by Bellarmine is not lawful.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
Whether Christ gave power only to the Pope, or to other ministers, too, is a moot argument, Hobbes implies, if it is considered outside common-wealths where the Pope is the sovereign power. A Pope only has the power to make laws if he is also the sovereign power of that common-wealth. If the Pope is not sovereign power, neither he, nor any other minister (unless they are the sovereign power), has power to make laws.  
In Hobbes’s estimation, the sovereign power of any given common-wealth has the authority to make laws in that common-wealth only. As the Pope has dominion over the subjects of Vatican City in Rome only, the power of the Pope cannot extend to people living in other common-wealths.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
According to Hobbes, Christ gave the Apostles and his Disciples the power to preach God’s Word; however, Christ did not give them power to command the people. All ministers and bishops (unless they are the sovereign power) get their power to preach and ordain from the sovereign power of the common-wealth in which they belong. This can be seen in Numbers 11, in which God commands Moses to select 70 Elders and infuse them with Moses’s spirit. As God’s Lieutenant, Moses was the sovereign power of the common-wealth of the Jews, and Moses gave the power to preach and ordain to the 70 Elders when he infused them with his spirit.
Hobbes claims that the ecclesiastical power of a Christian sovereign comes from God. As the sovereign power of the Jews, Moses’s ecclesiastical power comes from God, but the ecclesiastical power of the 70 Elders comes from Moses. Hobbes does not dispute that the Pope’s ecclesiastical power comes from God. What Hobbes does dispute is that the Pope’s power, like Moses’s, is limited and cannot extend beyond the people of his common-wealth. 
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
Cardinal Bellarmine claims the Church is like a monarchy and the Pope is the monarch, but Hobbes again disagrees. The Pope’s power is “Didacticall” only, and does not extend past this limitation. A Pope can never have jurisdiction, Hobbes argues, in the dominion of another sovereign power. A sovereign’s right to power is derived from the covenant of the people. If a Pope claims supreme power over the Christians in any given common-wealth, he dismisses the contract that joins them together. 
Hobbes’s claims that the Pope’s power is “Didacticall,” by which he means that the Pope’s power is purely ecclesiastical and is meant for teaching purposes only. Unless, of course, the Pope is operating in his own common-wealth, in which he is also the sovereign power. Otherwise, in other sovereigns’ dominions, the Pope’s word can only be counsel, not law.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
Literary Devices
If the Pope has absolute power, which is to say he has been granted such power by a sovereign, the Pope can depose princes and kings whenever he wants for whatever he wants. This is the precise argument offered by Cardinal Bellarmine and many others, Hobbes says, and Popes have historically put such power into practice. For instance, Pope Innocent III and the fourth Council of Lateran decried that any king under the Pope’s command was to rid their kingdom of heretics within one year or face excommunication. People cannot be expected to serve two different masters, Hobbes argues. To avoid this conflict, sovereign powers must keep all their power exclusively, including religious matters, or sovereign powers should give all their power to the Pope. To divide power is to destroy it and the common-wealth.    
Again, since the purpose of a common-wealth is to create a sovereign that is as powerful as possible, it does not make much sense for the sovereign to give any of that power away. In doing so, Hobbes maintains, the common-wealth is technically destroyed. Placing the Pope in a position of authority over all Christian sovereigns diminishes their power and dissolves their original covenants, in which case their subjects cannot be obligated to obey the Pope either. In short, Hobbes maintains it is impossible for the Pope to claim any power over other Christian sovereigns.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
Cardinal Bellarmine argues that the “Civill Power” of a sovereign is subject to the “Spirituall Power” of the Pope. Even if this were true, Hobbes says, that still doesn’t mean that the sovereign is obligated to obey the Pope. What Bellarmine means to say in his argument concerning the “Spirituall Power” of the Pope is that Pope has authority to command a sovereign power, and this, Hobbes implies, can never be.
In Hobbes’s opinion, having “Spirituall Power” over someone is not the same as having “Civil Power” over them. Spiritual power, like the power God has over Christians, does not technically exist until one becomes a spirit and enters into God’s Kingdome. Thus, even if the Pope had spiritual power over a sovereign, this power is ineffective in an earthly, civil sense.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
The Pope may very well be Christ’s only true minister, Hobbes says, but the Pope’s power doesn’t exist until Christ’s second coming. And even then, the power wouldn’t belong to the Pope of the present day, but to St. Peter and the rest of the Apostles, who will be the Judges in Christ’s Kingdome. Cardinal Bellarmine also argues that a spiritual common-wealth can take over a civil common-wealth if that common-wealth cannot rightly defend itself. Hobbes again disagrees.
Again, Hobbes sees a clear difference between spiritual power and civil power. The Pope only has authority in a spiritual world—not in the civil, earthly world that currently exists. In Hobbes’s opinion, there can be no crossover between the earthly, civil world and the spiritual world of God. The earthly civil world exists until Christ’s second coming, and only then can the spiritual world begin.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
According to Hobbes, there is no such thing as a “Spirituall Common-wealth,” at least not in this world. A “Spirituall Common-wealth” is just like the Kingdome of Christ, which even Christ says doesn’t exist in this world. Christ’s Kingdome will exist in the next world, after the Resurrection. A spiritual body cannot rise until the death of a natural body, Hobbes argues. Therefore, there can be no “Spirituall Common-wealth” for those who are still alive. 
Again, Hobbes argues that the Pope can claim no spiritual authority over Christians of other common-wealths while they are still alive. In their earthly existence, Christians are beholden to their earthly sovereign only, not the Pope or even God. One’s spiritual authority only has power over them once a subject has died. 
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
Cardinal Bellarmine also argues that it is unlawful for Christians to obey a heretical king, and that the Pope has the authority to decide what constitutes heresy. Hobbes claims this argument is categorically false. It goes against the Law of Nature for subjects of a common-wealth to disobey their sovereign power. Furthermore, it is the sovereign power, not the Pope, who has the authority to decide what is or isn’t considered heretical in a common-wealth.
Again, according to the Laws of Nature, only a sovereign has the power to decide what is heretical. The Laws of Nature also dictate that human beings must always obey their sovereign power. As God gave the Laws of Nature to humankind, Hobbes implies that Bellarmine’s claims of the Pope’s absolute power violate God’s laws as well as the Laws of Nature.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon
Hobbes examines several more examples of the Holy Scripture offered by Cardinal Bellarmine to prove his argument, and Hobbes’s conclusion each time is the same. A Pope can never have absolute power over people, unless he is also the sovereign power of a common-wealth. And, perhaps most importantly, a Pope can never have dominion over another sovereign power or the people residing in said sovereign’s common-wealth.
This passage recaps the heart of Hobbes’s argument: the Pope does not have authority over those outside his own common-wealth. For example, the Pope does not have dominion over the Christians of England, nor does the Pope have dominion over England’s sovereign, even if that sovereign is a Christian.
Themes
Power, Common-wealths, and Monarchies Theme Icon
Religion Theme Icon